“A Negro and by Consequence an Alien” - The legacy of Legal Race Making.

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
Yes.

First of all, it's not all that difficult to get a general idea of your ethnic background. You can start with a DNA testing service like 23andMe or Ancestry. Then find out what part(s) of the South your people come from. Then correlate that info with the maps and info here, beginning at section 16.

Secondly, I see myself as being born of a new people who primarily came into existence here, and whose experience and culture and sociopolitical situation is a product of that experience. While I prefer "Black ADOS" as a better term for those of us who have this background, I can accept "Black" for the time being. But I would never accept "Wolof" or "Igbo" or "Fente" or "Kongo" or any of those other African tribal designations, even if I could 100% genetically trace myself to one of them, since that is not my historical, cultural, or sociopolitical identity. And, my non-African ancestry is a part of that as well, regardless of how it came to be.

I get your answer but a couple of things... my understanding of the term designation is something given to you by another (in some cases for their own purposes). Black is a legal designation given to the enslaved Africans. Wolof or Igbo or Fente is what they are.

The other thing is...reading your post reminded me of something. Do you ever watch Star Trek-Voyager? The character 7 of 9 was described by a showrunner as a tragic figure. Assimilated into the Borg collective as a child and outfitted with cyborg implants she's actually more machine than human. She had no direct knowledge of being a human and thru out the show when presented with the idea of being addressed by her human name Annika Hanson she declined in favor of her Borg designation 7 of 9 - Tertiary Adjunct of Unimatrix 1. She found human culture (her true culture) alienating and unadaptable. A quote from an article on the character: She was deeply conflicted about whether she wanted to be human at all, and often longed for the order, community, and clarity of purpose that the Borg provided.

I guess it's easier to see something in a fictional character than in a people but I see a lot of parallels and similarities between Seven's life and the Black American experience. To see you reject embracing aspects of your African background and heritage in favor of a racial designation born of a new people who primarily came into existence in America seems similarly tragic at its core. And I know that most Black Americans (including myself to a degree) feel the same way. But I still acknowledge that the rejection of that is a sad thing.
 
Last edited:

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
In Re Warwick, a case decided by the court in 1669, the court's entire opinion was its one-sentence conclusion:

Hannah Warwick's case extenuated because she was overseen by a negro overseer.

The clear inference to be drawn from the decision is that the society was more interested in making sure that blacks did not exercise authority over whites, and that white servants knew this, than in prosecuting the infractions of Hannah Warwick. Thus, the court intimated, by extension, that whites, although wrong, could refuse to submit to the authority of blacks, even when blacks were performing as agents of the common master. If we err in the inference that Hannah Warwick was white, the case nevertheless exemplifies a debasement of blacks. For even if Hannah Warwick had been black, the court's view presumed that blacks were so inferior that the black overseer could not legally command the compliance even of another black.


The decision warned white masters that they should be reluctant to entrust to blacks any position of power and further communicated to white servants that the court would exonerate whites (or possibly blacks) who had committed wrongs while under the supervision of blacks. Thus, Warwick subscribes judicially to the view that the function of blacks in Virginia was to be ordered and never to order others.

Through the decisions of the colonial courts in Virginia during the first 50 years, the message became increasingly clear: the court's intent to promulgate legal doctrines was predicated on its assumption of the social standard that blacks were particularly inferior. By keeping its decisions consistent with that assumption, it made the legal sanctioning of slavery possible if not probable.

 
Last edited:

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
this is the full article in case WAPO blocks it for subscription service

Virginia Led the Way In Legal Oppression



By A. Leon Higginbotham Jr.
May 21, 1978
A HOMELAND of Thomas Jefferson, James Madison, George Washington and Patrick Henry. Virginia justifiably claims that from the earliest years it singularly provided significant leadership for all the colonies. In many ways, relatively, it was a model of agricultural and economic success as one of the first colonies. It played a major role in precipitating the American Revolution and in shaping the destiny of the new nation after 1776.
Yet, tragically, Virginia was also a leader in the gradual debasement of blacks through its ultimate institutionalization of slavery. It pioneered a legal process that assured blacks a uniquely degraded status - one in which the cruelties of slavery and pervasive racial injustice were guaranteed by its laws. Just as they emulated other aspects of Virginia's policies, many colonies would also followed Virginia's leadership in slavery law.
About the last of August, there came to Virginia a Dutchman of Warre that sold us twenty Negers.

John Rolfe, secretary and recorder of the Virginia colony, made the above entry toward the end of August 1619. It survives as the earliest known record dating the arrival of blacks at an American colony. These first "Negers," who arrived in Jamestown a year before the Pilgrims landed at Plymouth Rock, had not volunteered for the voyage. They had been brought to America unwillingly, captives of Dutchmen who had apparently seized them for a Spanish ship to sell them to the labor-short colonists.
In 1619, there was not as yet a statutory process to especially fix the legal standings of blacks. These first blacks were not exposed to the systematic degradation to which later blacks would be subjected. Yet they were not free. Where did they stand? After centuries of investigation and discussion, scholars are still unable to agree.
There is sufficient evidence to consider at least the possibility that these first black Jamestown arrivals, as well as many of those blacks who followed them in the next few decades, were treated by the early Jamestown colonists more or less as additions to the already existing social class into which whites had often been pressed - that of indentured servant. Some scholars have argued that for at least half a century the status of blacks in America remained incompletely defined - socially somewhere at the bottom of the white servant class perhaps, but nowhere near chattel slaves.

In 1641, the colonial court decided on one of the most fascinating cases of this era. In re Graweere was a pivotal case in that it highlighted the ambiguities of the black man's position in Virginia during the early years. While under the law he was not the complete equal of the white man, nevertheless he had not been fully stripped of all basic human rights. John Graweere, a "negro servant unto William Evans," petitioned the court for permission to purchase the freedom of his young child from a Lieutenant Sheppard, the owner of the child's mother, in order that the child "should be made a Christian and be brought up in the fear of God and in the knowledge of religion taught and exercised by the church of England." The court ruled in favor of Graweere's petition and ordered:

that the child shall be free from the said Evans or his assigns and to be and remain at the disposing and education of the said Graweere and the child's godfather - who undertaketh to see it brought up in the Christian religion as aforesaid.

Graweere illustrates the judicial system's early flexibility and its approval of masters who designed a labor system that gave even black servants or slaves some rights and privileges and their masters some rights to manumit. Yet the same legal process that sanctioned the right of Graweere's master to allow his slave some degree of economic autonomy also sanctioned the right of other masters to impose perpetual servitude on blacks by will or contract. To be sure, a will or a contract was only an expression of the maker's desire and intent, and not a judicial or legislative pronouncement. yet the presence and presumed validity of these agreements is significant for they reveal that, prior to any statutory authorization, blacks were being "singled out for special treatment which suggests a general debasement of Negroes as a group." For instance, in a 1646 contract, Francis Potts sold a black woman and child to Stephen Carlton, "to the use of him forever." Another deed records William Whittington's sale of a girl merely 10 years old; looking to the future he noted that she was sold along with any issue (children) she might produce for her and her children's "lifetime and their successors forever."

In 1640, the Virginia Court demonstrated that it would not be reluctant to subject blacks who were not already enslaved to lifetime servitude. In Re Negro John Punch, three runaway servants, two white and one black (John Punch), were captured in Maryland and each sentenced to be whipped; but the judicial parity stopped with the whipping. The court then went on to impose different sentences for the same "crime":
one called Victor, a dutchman, the other a Scotchman called James Gregory, shall first serve out their times with their master according to their Indentures, and one whole year apiece after the time of their service is Expired . . . and after that service . . . to serve the colony for three whole years apiece, and that the third being a negro called John Punch shall serve his said master or his assigns for the time of his natural Life here or elsewhere.
Thus, although he committed the same crime as the Dutchman and the Scotsman, John Punch, a black man, was sentenced to lifetime slavery. For the white servants, an additional four years of service was deemed sufficient punishment.

In Re Warwick, a cease decided by the court in 1669, the court's entire opinion was its one-sentence conclusion:
Hannah Warwick's case extenuated because she was overseen by a negro overseer.
The clear inference to be drawn from the decision is that the society was more interested in making sure that blacks did not exercise authority over whites, and that white servants knew this, than in prosecuting the infractions of Hannah Warwick. Thus, the court intimated, by extension, that whites, although wrong, could refuse to submit to the authority of blacks, even when blacks were performing as agents of the common master. If we err in the inference that Hannah Warwick was white, the case nevertheless exemplifies a debasement of blacks. For even if Hannah Warwick had been black, the court's view presumed that blacks were so inferior that the black overseer could not legally command the compliance even of another black.

The decision warned white masters that they should be reluctant to entrust to blacks any position of power, and further communicated to white servants that the court would exonerate whites (or possibly blacks) who had committed wrongs while under the supervision of blacks. Thus, Warwick subscribes judicially to the view that the function of blacks in Virginia was to be ordered and never to order others.
Through the decisions of the colonial courts in Virginia during the first 50 years, the message became increasingly clear: the court's intent to promulgate legal doctrines was predicated on its assumption of the social standard that blacks were particularly inferior. By keeping its decisions consistent with that assumption, it made the legal sanctioning of slavery possible if not probable.
IT WAS NOT UNTIL 1659, 40 years after the arrival of the first blacks in Virginia, that a direct reference to blacks as slaves appeared in Virginia legislation. A 1659 statute imposed reduced import duties on merchants bringing slaves into the colony:

Act XVI. Dutch and all strangers of Christian nations are allowed free trade if they give bond and pay impost of ten shillings per hogshead laid upon all tobacco exported to any foreign dominions; always provided that if Dutch or other foreigners shall import any Negro slaves they, the said Dutch or other foreigners, shall for the tobacco really produced by the said Negroes, pay only the impost of two shillings per hogshead, the like being paid by our own nation.

The purpose of this statute was to encourage the international slave trade by providing financial incentives to the "Dutch and all strangers of Christian nations" participating in the slave trade. But of greater significance historically is the fact that this statute clearly reflects legislative recognition of the increasing value slave labor had acquired in colonial Virginia.
By 1660, it appears, the composition of the labor force in colonial Virginia - previously made up of white and blacks in various degrees of servitude - began in include in increasing numbers another category of laborers, blacks in lifetime bondage. The eventual crossover to an almost total slave labor force would not be complete, it seems, until a century later. The statutes of the next few years, therefore, while reflecting recognition, if not direct sanctioning, of perpetual servitude for some black laborers, concern themselves not with the minority of black slaves but with what were the special problems during the period of the transition - when white indentured servants, black servants and totally enslaved blacks worked side by side. One of the problems was apparently white-black alliances for the purposes of escape.

In 1660, a statute dealt with one of the early attempts of the legislature to put a stop to such attempts.
Act XXII. It is enacted that in case any English servant shall run away in company with any Negroes who are incapable of making satisfaction by addition of time that the English so running away shall serve for the time of the Negroes' absence as they are to do for their own by a former act.
The reference to "Negroes who are incapable of making satisfaction by addition of time" is an implicit acknowledgment of negro lifetime servitude, which some scholars have interpreted further to be an actual expression of legal recognition of Negro slavery.
THE MOST MAJOR slave codes were dated 1680-1682. They not only synthesized all the piecemeal legislative deprivations of the previous 20 years but introduced others incorporating some of the harshest customs and traditions that had evolved to control the colony's indentured servants. At the same time, the codes were emphatic in denying slaves any of the privileges or rights that had accrued to white indentured servants in this same period.

Despite some limitations on their rights, white servants were never the victims of any legislative plan to deprive them of such basic options as the right to sue one's masters for ill-treatment or for one's freedom, and white servants were never precluded from owning property. Nor does the argument that masters feared slave revolts, which of course could destroy the colony, fully explain why the legislature denied basic rights to blacks, mulattoes, and Indians while granting some of those privileges to white indentured servants.

An argument can just as easily be made that the white indentured servant or freedman precluded from the decision-making processes of the government and subjected to harsher treatment was probably as dangerous as the slave. Certainly, the totality of deprivations cannot be explained by any assumption that blacks were more necessarily prone to violence. There is no evidence to substantiate this. And whatever the relative threats posed by each group, the fact is that nonwhites alone were legally deprived of all basic human rights. Only against nonwhites did colonial society feel it could use anything and everything - the legal structure, the militia, even armed private citizens - to keep human beings in a submissive state.
With each succeeding decade, the Virginia legislators, expressing a mixture of fear, greed and prejudice, simply reduced the privileges and rights of blacks. They rationalized their actions on the ground of security, without religious or moral qualms whatsoever. They no doubt convinced themselves that blacks were so inferior that their subhuman status deserved no recognition of human rights. And just as often, they probably made no effort at all to find a rationale; they simply dehumanized those who were black because of the color of their skins and because blacks were largely powerless to prevent it.

It may be no more than the accident of black skin that precluded the empathy of white Virginians. The black looked enough different from the white Virginian to spare the white any guilt over his legal cannibalism. The white Virginian, enriching himself by depriving blacks of rights, was further spared by the convenient differences in skin color and hair texture from having the thought cross his mind: "There but for the grace of God go I."
The 1680 statute would become the model of repression throughout the South for the next 180 years. The following provisions are illustrative of its codification of prejudice and the degree to which the statute attempted to make sure that blacks would be recognized as legally inferior:

Act X. Whereas the frequent meetings of considerable numbers of Negro slaves under pretense of feasts and burials is judged of dangerous consequence [be it] enacted that no Negro or slave may carry arms, such as any club, staff, gun, sword or other weapon, nor go from his owner's plantation without a certificate and then only on necessary occasions; the punishment twenty lashes on the bare back, well lain on. And further, if any Negro lift up his hand against any Christian he shall receive thirty lashes, and if he absent himself or lie out from his master's service and resist lawful apprehension, he may be killed and this law shall be published every six months.

If blacks could not leave the owner's plantation without a certificate, their mobility was destroyed; if blacks could not carry arms, the potential to resist was reduced. And, if blacks could be whipped for lifting up a hand against any Christian - regardless of the provocation - then the dehumanization process was complete because blacks were legally precluded from responding in a manner thought normal for whites or most other human beings.
DATA INDICATE that almost from the time blacks arrived in Virginia there were interracial sexual relations between Indians, blacks and whites.
In a struggling colony where the population was largely composed of Europe's undesirables and where women were scarce, it is unclear whether illegitimacy, per se, was so great a stigma. However, the colonial assembly thought sexual relations between whites and blacks to be special problems requiring a special penalty:

Act XII. Children got by an Englishman upon a Negro woman shall be bond or free according to the condition of the mother, and if any Christian shall commit fornication with a Negro man or woman, he shall pay double the fines of a former act.
This statute, upon first reading, does not clearly reveal the built-in bias and preferences of its drafters. "Englishmen" as used here is probably a synonym for whites generally or at least white Englishmen. The fact that interracial fornication caused a double fine corroborates the thesis that an interracial sexual act was considered to be far more immoral or deviant than fornication by persons of the same race.

The statute also expressed more than mere social taboos or religious precepts. Implicit in the statute were the economic preferences and advantages to whites who sought to extend servitude and slavery. Prior to the passage of this statute, it had been an open question as to whether the normal doctrine of English law would be applicable - that the status of a child would be dependent upon the status of the child's father.
Because (at least in part) of the scarcity of white women, there was probably more sexual contact between Englishmen and black women than between white women and black men. It was, therefore, significant from an economic standpoint whether a child derived its status from its mother or its father. Once it was established that the black woman's child took the mother's status, the master class gained a crucial economic advantage - its labor force reproduced itself. If the legislature had followed the English legal doctrine that the status of the child was determined by the status of the father, the thousands of blacks or mulattoes whose fathers were white would have been free. The subsequent 1691 statute (Act XVI) was far more comprehensive. By the language of its preamble, it was designed to prevent "that abominable mixture and spurious issue . . . by Negroes, mulattoes and Indians intermarrying with English or other white women" and provided that:
whatsoever English or other white man or woman, bond or free, shall intermarry with a Negro, mulatto, or Indian man or woman, bond or free, he shall within three months be banished from this dominion forever.

And it is further enacted, that if any English woman being free shall have a bastard child be a Negro she shall pay fifteen pounds to the church wardens, and in default of such payment, she shall be taken into possession by the church wardens and disposed of for five years and the amount she brings shall be paid one-third to their majesties for the support of the government, one-third to the parish where the offense is committed and the other third to the informer. The child shall be bound out by the church wardens until he is 30 years of age. In case the English woman that shall have a bastard is a servant she shall be sold by the church wardens (after her time is expired) for five years, and the child serve as aforesaid.
Several racial disparities were written into this statute. After 1691, the white man or woman was to be penalized if he or she legitimized the relationship with a black person by marriage; in that event, they would be banished from the colony forever. Yet, apparently, the white man could remain in the colony if he merely carried on a meretricious relationship with a black woman. The possibility of pregnancy significantly lessened the white woman's chances of maintaining a clandestine relationship with a black man. Yet, the statute did not penalize a white man for having sexual relations with his slave and it was not a crime for a black woman to have a bastard child by a white man. Both acts became a crime only when a white English woman had a black man's child out of wedlock.

EVEN BEFORE 1700, the Virginia legislature had begun to attack the normal human emotions of blacks by attempting to deprive slaves of any hope of eventual emancipation. It did this by temporarily and conveniently reversing its philosophy and legislating that one right, at least, of the property holder was not inviolable - the right to give up his interest in his property. Legislation of 1699, in fact, had made manumission impossible in some instances: previously the master's right to determine the nature and length of servitude imposed on his slaves had not been challenged.
By 1691, there was an absolute prohibition against freeing a black or mulatto without also providing for transportation of "the negro out of the country within six months after such setting free." Free blacks were viewed as undesirable elements in the population, a clear indication that racist attitudes had hardened. The implication of such a statute is obvious - blacks had only one function in Virginia society and that was to labor perpetually for the benefit of their owners.

Later provisions further limited the master's right to manumit his slaves. Manumission became possible only upon approval of the governor and council as a reward for public service, which included, by definition, revealing a slave conspiracy. Slaves were punished when their masters ignored such statutory mandates. The legislature authorized the seizure and re-enslavement of blacks, mulattoes, and Indians who had been improperly freed.

NOT ONLY DID the Virginia council fail to enact legislation to protect slaves, the council enacted no legislation at all extending to slaves any of the rights granted to servants. In fact, as far as slaves were concerned, the 1705 statute increased their master's control over their lives. For example, Chapter 34 provided that a master who killed his slave in an attempt to correct the slave would not be held to have committed a felony.
Virginia's 1705 statute exemplifies the "maturation" of the Virginians' legislative process and their views of blacks as nonhuman beings. They seemed to view blacks as if they were fungible products - just like trees, tobacco or other disposable commodities. They seemed horrified over the fact that some slaves would become "incorrigible," without ever pausing to question why.

Did the legislature in 1705 think that blacks might also have an innate desire for freedom - just as their white masters sought it? Was it the lust by blacks for freedom which made them incorrigible? The language of statutes so often masks the human suffering which is imposed by statutory fiat. The statute permitted the court to sanction punishment for the purpose of "terrifying other blacks" - terrifying them so that they would not become incorrigible so that they would not dare to seek freedom.

Thus the judicial system, which historically is cited as a refuge of justice for the weak and dispossessed, was utilized by colonial Virginia to sanction brutalizing blacks rather than to protect them. One obligation did remain for the court. The legislature recognized at least one type of value inherent in each slave. It provided that:
for every slave killed, in pursuance of this act, or put to death by law, the master or owner of such slave shall be paid by the public.
Thus, by their statute of 1705 the legislature most carefully protected the economic values of the master and disregarded the human value of a slave's life.
 

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
NOT ONLY DID the Virginia council fail to enact legislation to protect slaves, the council enacted no legislation at all extending to slaves any of the rights granted to servants. In fact, as far as slaves were concerned, the 1705 statute increased their master's control over their lives. For example, Chapter 34 provided that a master who killed his slave in an attempt to correct the slave would not be held to have committed a felony.
Virginia's 1705 statute exemplifies the "maturation" of the Virginians' legislative process and their views of blacks as nonhuman beings. They seemed to view blacks as if they were fungible products - just like trees, tobacco or other disposable commodities. They seemed horrified over the fact that some slaves would become "incorrigible," without ever pausing to question why.

Did the legislature in 1705 think that blacks might also have an innate desire for freedom - just as their white masters sought it? Was it the lust by blacks for freedom which made them incorrigible? The language of statutes so often masks the human suffering which is imposed by statutory fiat. The statute permitted the court to sanction punishment for the purpose of "terrifying other blacks" - terrifying them so that they would not become incorrigible so that they would not dare to seek freedom.

Thus the judicial system, which historically is cited as a refuge of justice for the weak and dispossessed, was utilized by colonial Virginia to sanction brutalizing blacks rather than to protect them. One obligation did remain for the court. The legislature recognized at least one type of value inherent in each slave. It provided that:
for every slave killed, in pursuance of this act, or put to death by law, the master or owner of such slave shall be paid by the public.
Thus, by their statute of 1705 the legislature most carefully protected the economic values of the master and disregarded the human value of a slave's life.

316 YEARS LATER:
2020-06-13-blmprotests-uk.jpg
 

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
The Social Construction of Whiteness: Racism by Intent, Racism by Consequence

Abstract The discipline of Sociology has generated great contributions to scholarship and research about American race relations. Much of the theorizing on American race relations in America is expressed in binary terms of black and white. Historically, the study of American race relations typically problematizes the “othered” status, that is, the non-white status in America’s racial hierarchy. However, the sociology of race relations has historically failed to take into account both sides of the black/white binary paradigm when addressing racial inequality. In other words, in the case of race, it becomes difficult to see the forest for the trees. Thus, in Sociology, we find less scholarship about the role “whiteness as the norm” plays in sustaining social privilege beyond that which is accorded marginalized others. In order to examine the historical black/white binary paradigm of race in America, it is important to understand its structuration. This article extends the applicability of sociologies of knowledge (Thomas Theorem, social constructionism) and Gidden’s structuration theory to inform a postmodern
 

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
White by Law The Legal Construction of Race


Nevertheless, the tendency to treat race as a pre-legal phenomenon is coming to an end. Of late, a new strand of legal scholarship dedicated to reconsidering of the role of race in U.S. society has emerged. Writers in this genre, known as critical race theory, have for the most part shown an acute awareness of the socially constructed nature of race. Much critical race theory scholarship recognizes that race is a legal construction. For example, a recent article by Gerald Torres and Kathryn Milun examines the imposition of the legal concept of “tribe” on the Mashpee of Massachusetts. In order to proceed in a suit over alienated lands, the Mashpee were required to prove their existence as a tribe in legal terms that focused on racial purity, hierarchical leadership, and clearly demarcated geographic boundaries. This legal definition of tribal identity ineluctably led to their nonexistence of the Mashpee people, since it “incorporated specific perceptions regarding race, leadership, community, and territory that were entirely alien to Mashpee culture.” Because the Mashpee did not conform to the racial and cultural stereotypes that infuse the law, they could not prove their existence in those terms, and hence did not exist as a people capable of suing in federal court. The article documents the manner in which Mashpee legal identity---and more, their existence---depended upon a particular definition of race and tribe, thus unearthing the manner in which law mediates racial and tribal ontology. This recognition of the role of law in the social dynamics of racial identity arguably lies near the heart of critical race theory. As John Calmore argues, “Critical race theory begins with a recognition that ‘race’ is not a fixed term. Instead, ‘race’ is a fluctuating, decentered complex of social meanings that are formed and transformed under the constant pressures of political struggle.” Critical race theory increasingly acknowledges the extent to which race is not an independent given on which the law acts, but rather a social construction at least in part fashioned by law.

 

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
Facing America's History of Racism Requires Facing the Origins of 'Race' as a Concept


The logic behind the history of race initially seems deceivingly clear: to justify the forced deportation of 400,000 Black Africans to North America (and another eleven million to other parts of the Americas between 1525 and 1866), Europeans and their American heirs found it necessary to debase and revile their captives. Yet today’s racism is more than a malignant byproduct of the 19th-century American plantation system; it also grew out of an elaborate and supposedly “scientific” European conception of the human species that began during the Enlightenment.


By the early decades of the 18th century, the Continent’s savants and natural philosophers no longer automatically looked to the Bible to explain the story of the human species. Intent on finding physical explanations for natural phenomena, naturalists employed more “empirical” methods to solve one of the biggest “anthropological” questions of the day: why did people from Africa, millions of whom were already toiling in European plantations, look different from white Europeans?

By the 1740s, one could find a dozen or more purportedly scientific explanations. Some claimed that blackness came from vapors emanating from the skin; others claimed that black skin was passed on from generation to generation via the power of the maternal imagination or from darkened sperm; still others asserted that the heat or the air of the Torrid Zone darkened the humors and stained the skin.

The dominant “anthropological” concept that emerged around 1750 was called degeneration, which can be understood as the precise opposite of what we now know to be true about humankind’s origins. In contrast to the model that shows how evolution and successive human migrations from the African continent account for humanity’s many colors, degeneration theory maintained that there was an original and superior white race, and that this group of humans moved about the globe and mutated in different climates. These morphological and pigmentation changes were not seen as adaptations or the results of natural selection; they were explained as a perversion or deterioration of a higher archetype.

Medical practitioners stepped in to flesh out that vague narrative, creating the basis for the idea of what we now call race. Anatomists, in particular, dissected the bodies of supposedly degenerated Africans, and published numerous now-shocking articles on the supposed damage of living in a tropical climate: black brains, black bile, black sperm and even race-specific black lice.

The most bigoted of European physicians attributed specific organ-based liabilities to Black Africans, including indolence and diminished cognition. Not surprisingly, these falsehoods and the methods that produced them flourished in the United States: in 1851, Samuel A. Cartwright identified two “diseases” associated with Africans. The first was a mental illness he dubbed drapetomania, which caused slaves to run away. The second was dysaesthesia aethiopica, a type of lethargy that struck Africans who were not enslaved or overseen by whites. His cure: anointing them with oil, and applying a leather strap.

Europe also bequeathed Americans with the very category of “race.” By the 1770s, German figureheads including Emmanuel Kant and J.F. Blumenbach—the latter of whom coined the term Caucasian because he believed that the original prototype race originated in the Caucus Region—affirmed that new biometric and anatomical discoveries justified the use of the modernistic word race to distinguish among human subspecies.

Racial classification schemes provided the most powerful framework for understanding the divide between white and Black. Some naturalists took this one step further, proposing that Africans actually formed a different species entirely. Predictably, this latter idea was adopted by some members of the proslavery lobby in the United States.


Progressive thinkers, abolitionists and, eventually, formerly enslaved people including the writer Olaudah Equiano began critiquing the roots and effects of racial prejudice as early as the 1770s. And yet, even as scientific research has confirmed just how wrong Enlightenment theories of race were, many of the most rearguard and unscientific European notions regarding race have remained deeply embedded in the American psyche, not to mention in the arsenal of the Alt Right. Indeed, the immigration policies of the Trump Administration, in insisting that immigrants from certain countries are less desirable than others, are effectively resurrecting centuries-old notions about the supposedly deterministic nature of race.

 
Last edited:

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
The Disturbing Resilience of Scientific Racism
A new book explores how racist biases continue to maintain a foothold in research today

Scientists, including those who study race, like to see themselves as objectively exploring the world, above the political fray. But such views of scientific neutrality are naive, as study findings, inevitably, are influenced by the biases of the people conducting the work.

The American sociologist W. E. B. Du Bois once wrote, “The problem of the twentieth century is the problem of the color line.” His words were borne out, in part, by science. It was the century when the scientifically backed enterprise of eugenics—improving the genetic quality of white, European races by removing people deemed inferior—gained massive popularity, with advocates on both sides of the Atlantic. It would take the Holocaust to show the world the logical endpoint of such horrific ideology, discrediting much race-based science and forcing eugenics’ most hardline adherents into the shadows.


The post-war era saw scientists on the right-wing fringe find ways to cloak their racist views in more palatable language and concepts. And as Angela Saini convincingly argues in her new book, Superior: The Return of Race Science, published May 21 by Beacon Press, the “problem of the color line” still survives today in 21st-century science.

In her thoroughly researched book, Saini, a London-based science journalist, provides clear explanations of racist concepts while diving into the history of race science, from archaeology and anthropology to biology and genetics. Her work involved poring through technical papers, reports and books, and interviewing numerous scientists across various fields, sometimes asking uncomfortable questions about their research.

“Mainstream scientists, geneticists and medical researchers still invoke race and use these categories in their work, even though we have been told for 70 years that they have no biological meaning, that they have only social meaning,” Saini says.

Scientific research has struggled with concepts of race for centuries, often proposing misleading or erroneous explanations of racial differences. Contentious debates among Europeans about the origins of modern humans began in the 19th century, and many of the continent’s leading scientists believed firmly that Europeans exemplified the most evolved and intelligent humans. Human fossils in Europe provided the first data points in the budding field of paleoanthropology, but the region was in reality just where European archaeologists happened to start looking. Fossils, as well as cave art, DNA samples and other evidence later uncovered around the world pointed to a more complex picture of human origins: Elements of modern humans emerged throughout Africa, and those people migrated east and then north and west in waves.

Rather than distinct races, groupings or borders, the continually mixing populations produced only gradients, with some traits slightly more common in some regions than others. Lighter skin color in northern climates emerged late; some Britons were shocked to learn that Cheddar Man, the remains of a man who lived in southwest England almost 10,000 years ago, would today have been considered black.

In the 1950s, geneticists began to confirm what some archaeologists had already surmised: “Individual variation within population groups, overlapping with other population groups, turned out to be so large that the boundaries of race made less and less sense,” Saini writes. The conclusion was that no “pure” races exist that are distinct from others. Despite this evidence, those eugenicists still practicing sought to prevent their supposedly superior race from being overrun by immigration, miscegenation and higher birth rates among other ethnicities.

While few people study or advocate for eugenics today, some scientists in the rapidly advancing field of genetics held onto related ideologies after World War II. They simply used different terms, Saini points out, as some continued with race-focused research while referring to “populations” and “human variation” rather than “races” and “racial differences.” Geneticist James Watson, for instance, a co-discoverer of DNA’s double helix structure, has frequently been the subject of withering criticism for voicing racist beliefs, including that differences on tests of intelligence have a racial component, and arguing that Indians are servile and that Chinese people have somehow become genetically conformist.

A handful of researchers with similar beliefs, including former Nazi scientist Otmar von Verschuer and British eugenicist Roger Pearson, had trouble getting their research published in reputable journals and formed their own journal in 1961. Mankind Quarterly became a platform for race science—a place to publish questionable research under the trappings of objective science. Intelligence, a more respected psychology journal that’s published by the major publishing company Elsevier, also occasionally included papers with pseudoscientific findings about intelligence differences between races. Until recently, that journal had two eugenics supporters, Gerhard Heisenberg and Richard Lynn, on its editorial board. But by the time Saini finished her book late last year, after interviewing the journal’s editor-in-chief, she saw that the pair had been removed from the journal’s list of board members.

“The extreme stuff poses a dilemma for legitimate scientists, since you can’t read every crank’s work and falsify it,” says Aaron Panofsky, a sociologist of science at UCLA and author of the book, Misbehaving Science: Controversy and the Development of Behavior Genetics. Researchers don’t want to endow these papers with more legitimacy than they deserve, but they don’t want to ignore them and risk fueling conspiracy theories, either.

While Mankind Quarterly has managed to hang on into the 21st century, “hard-core scientific racists are mostly old white men, and they’re not being reproduced in academia,” Panofsky says. Even so, plenty of racist, young white men continue to promote concepts of scientific racism, such as the participants in the 2017 Unite the Right rally in Charlottesville, Virginia—an event that even the scientific journal Nature felt the need to condemn.

Even more well-meaning epidemiological scientists nonetheless still use race as a crude proxy for myriad social and environmental factors. Saini cites an example of a 2017 study with statistical errors claiming that race and biology indicate that the airways of asthmatic black Americans become more inflamed than those of asthmatic white Americans. Black Americans do suffer more from asthma than whites do, but they’re also affected more by environmental hazards like air pollution from highways and factories as well as disparities in access to high-quality healthcare. These many forms of inequality and structural racism—which sociologists have documented for decades—were swept under the rug in favor of a race variable that led to findings that could be easily misinterpreted.

In another example, Saini describes the ill-fated 1990s Human Genome Diversity Project, which analyzed the genetic variations of small, remote populations referred to as “isolates,” including the Basques in Europe, the Kurds of eastern Turkey and Native American tribes. Indigenous rights activists, understandably sensitive to being exploited, resisted the project, surprising the naive scientists.

Time and time again, groupings by race, even if they don’t use the term “race,” can be dangerous and misleading to people looking for inherent biological differences. But Saini doesn’t think we can be “colorblind” or “post-race” in scientific research either. Scientists who claim to be so tend to have the same problem as the asthma study, ignoring racial inequalities all around that influence a study’s findings. Saini also explores the possibility of affirmative action policies, reparations or environmental justice advocacy, all intended to mitigate structural, historical and scientific racism.

Like many geneticists, Saini argues that since race is a social construct, it doesn’t belong in genetics research. Scientists in other fields have the freedom to study race, she writes, but with that freedom comes responsibility. They can’t afford to leave room for misinterpretation. Researchers using racial categories “should fully understand what they mean, be able to define them, and know their history,” Saini writes.

The rest of us, too, need to be aware of racial stereotypes, lest we fall prey to them. “That’s part of the reason that we’re fascinated by DNA ancestry testing,” Saini says. “The reason it matters to us is because we feel that these racial categories have some meaning, that they can tell us something about ourselves, and that’s just wrong. They can’t.”

 
Last edited:

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
Gaelic Scotland in the Colonial Imagination: Anglophone Writing from 1600 to 1900


Demographically, colonialism can involve considerable movements of population, often across vast geographical and cultural distances. For instance, people from the mother country moved to colonial dependencies, either temporarily or permanently. Sometimes, this happened in smaller numbers to fulfill key positions in “controlling” a labor force which was still largely indigenous, as in British India. Elsewhere, more extensive resettlement was used to rid the mother country of “superfluous” population (criminals or paupers) that might be more profitably settled elsewhere, to stabilize the colonizer’s control against the competing interests of indigenous populations or other colonial powers, or to replace local forms of production that were not sufficiently profitable to the colonizer with more lucrative systems imported from the mother country, as happened when certain Native American or Aboriginal Australian hunter-gatherer economies were replaced with European farming systems and imported European farmers. Resettlement can be voluntary, as with some of the European “pioneer” farmers who hoped for better life chances, or enforced, as with deported British criminals, Native Americans resettled on “reservations,” or the millions of enslaved Africans shipped to the New World as a colonial labor force. Often enough, colonial demographic displacements grew to the dimension of genocide through loss of land (entailing poverty and starvation), outrageously bad travel conditions (as on the Middle Passage), imported diseases, and outright slaughter.

The hierarchization of different population groups was often shored up by the construction of supposedly innate “racial” biological distinctions between them which placed these groups in a “natural” hierarchy and justified the maltreatment of the “lower” orders on this “racial” ladder. Colonialism also involves the construction of cultural hierarchies: the colonizer’s language(s) and cultural forms are claimed to be superior, while those of the colonized are systematically devalued and discriminated against. Sometimes this can be a mere corollary of material hierarchies: the dominant 8 Introduction power imposes the terms of interaction, and colonizers who were too lazy to learn the colony’s language(s) had the means to pressure locals to learn the colonizers’ language(s) instead. Here as well, the highly unequal terms of colonial culture contact become obvious. Cultural hierarchies can also help to legitimate and stabilize material hierarchies. The claim that one culture is worth more than the other can boost the colonizer’s sense of supremacy and assuage potential pangs of guilt about the treatment of the colonized, thus deflecting the risk of anticolonial critique within the colonizer’s own ranks. If the colonizer manages to instill his ideas of cultural hierarchies among the colonized, the latter can come to believe in their own inferiority, which can reduce the risk of resistance: such colonized subjects may either conceive the ambition to imitate the colonizer and voluntarily discard their own culture, or at least resign themselves to their subordinate status even if imitating the colonizer is beyond their wishes or means (e.g., because they cannot afford a European education). Hierarchies between different population groups can also be shored up by exaggerating the extent of the cultural differences that lie between them: colonial ideologies often construct colonizer and colonized as exact opposites, setting up a binary distinction between self and “Other”; and such claims of absolute cultural distinctness are used to legitimate social distinctions, similar to the way that claims of “racial” distinctions are used. Postcolonial scholarship refers to these and related processes as “othering,” often spelling the constructed “Other” with a capital letter.

 

mangobob79

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
As a Black person how would you feel if you found out your Black colonial ancestors owned slaves??
Legal race making became a distinctive feature of Atlantic slave societies, reducing Africans and their descendants to “negroes,” “negros,” “nègres,” or “noirs,” subjects without history, honor, or genealogy. Blackness obliterated and flattened a multitude of cultures, languages, histories, and experiences into a single legally defined, socially constituted category of degradation.7 Across linguistic and imperial barriers, the law constituted “blacks” as social outcasts, conflating their social existence with enslavement. Legal prohibitions that applied to “all black men and women, free or enslaved,” or defined certain actions by “any black or mulatto” against “whites” as a crime, made blackness, rather than enslavement, the mark of degradation.

I'm posting this again for this question:

Considering the history and how the enslaved Africans can to be "black"....if you could connect with your roots and know the details of the various countries, tribes, and people of your ethnic background....

WOULD YOU STILL WANT TO IDENTIFY WITH BEING "BLACK"?
came in this thread from the rogan/peterson "BLACK" one to further see wtf ure actually tryin to say :D
okay , u raise interesting points but i believe ure overlooking alot of other things in assigning the wrong metric to the utility of the word BLACK
 

geechiedan

Rising Star
BGOL Investor
came in this thread from the rogan/peterson "BLACK" one to further see wtf ure actually tryin to say :D
okay , u raise interesting points but i believe ure overlooking alot of other things in assigning the wrong metric to the utility of the word BLACK
what am I overlooking?
 
Top