Trump SCOTUS nominee Neil Gorsuch -The "Frozen Black Man" Trucker Case

muckraker10021

Superstar *****
BGOL Investor
170321101244-neil-gorsuch-confirmation-hearing-2-horizontal-gallery.jpg



Come on peeps......you all been watching political tv for decades.....you know what's going on.
That Black women (whoever she is) is intentionally seated there by the cac judges federalist society handlers so that she will appear in every camera shot of the judge. It is a visual subliminal messaging technique designed to soften his racist pedigree and judicial record. When he was a student at Columbia University in Manhattan in New York, the judge was OPPOSED to economic sanctions against the white-supremacist apartheid government of South Africa; he was OPPOSED to the release of Nelson Mandela; he was in his 20's then, —now he's just a racist older cac judge about to be put on the SCOTUS for life.



This thread is now two pages long http://www.bgol.us/forum/index.php?...tential-supreme-court-justice-gorsuch.942010/and
NONE of you peeps has mentioned Judge Gorsuch's hideous barbaric ruling in the "Frozen Trucker" case.

The man below is
Alphonse Maddin.

maxresdefault.jpg


Mr. Maddin was a truck driver employed by the TransAm trucking corporation.

Late on a January night in temperatures below zero, he discovered that his trailer’s brakes had locked up due to the sub zero cold weather (-12 degrees). (The truck itself could drive but not when attached to the trailer).

He called TransAm’s road service for help at 11:17 p.m., and then discovered that the truck cabin’s heat was broken. He fell asleep and woke up two hours later with a numb torso from the sub-zero weather. Mr. Maddin also could not feel his feet or toes.

He called the road service again, and they told him to “hang in there” despite the life-threatening conditions.

He waited about 30 more minutes before unhitching the broken trailer. Although his supervisor ordered him to stay, Maddin decided to drive off with the truck after almost three hours in the subzero cold, he thought he would freeze to death.


TransAm fired Maddin for abandoning his trailer.

Mr. Maddin, claimed he was wrongfully fired after he disregarded a supervisor's instructions to stay with a broken down trailer, despite sub-zero freezing temperatures inside the trailer and outside.

Seven judges on the 10th circuit agreed that Mr. Maddin had been illegally fired.

Judge Gorsuch dissented from the seven judges. He said the Mr. Maddin should of followed company rules and either stayed in the unheated truck or drive a brakeless tractor trailer on the highway.

Gorsuch said- "Our only task is to decide whether the decision was an illegal one," "There's simply no law anyone has pointed us to giving employees the right to operate their vehicles in ways their employers forbid."


ap17080705271945.jpg

Gorsuch




 

COINTELPRO

Transnational Member
Registered
61P63CVDz6S._SL1500_.jpg

-font-b-Car-b-font-font-b-Heater-b-font-font-b-Car-b-font.jpg

If I was a trucker, buy a lithium battery, put flexible solar panels on truck. Plenty of videos on YouTube.

The best thing to do is post your experience online so people can avoid the company.

This would be a good business opportunity to develop this backup or could be used at night.
 
Last edited:

QueEx

Rising Star
Super Moderator
header-ie8.png
t
Sunday, Mar 26, 2017 11:00 AM CDT

Gorsuch, Thomas, Rehnquist and beyond:

A short history of right-wing lies in
Supreme
Court confirmation hearings

Neil Gorsuch's bland denials belong to a tradition of
conservative dishonesty that reaches back many decades

Paul Rosenberg

rehnquist-roberts-thomas-620x412.jpg

William Rehnquist; John Roberts; Clarence Thomas (Credit: AP/Larry Downing/Susan Walsh)


As Neil Gorsuch tries to avoid confronting his record in his campaign to steal Merrick Garland’s Supreme Court seat, it’s helpful to gain a broader view of a profoundly deceptive multi-decade conservative drama, in which this episode is but one tiny part. To understand that drama, we must begin with what it has risen up against.

In 1954, something truly remarkable happened. While America’s political system was still being held hostage by proud, self-identified racists, a full decade after we fought Nazi Germany in World War II, a bipartisan Supreme Court unanimously declared that segregated schools were unconstitutional in Brown vs. Board of Education. A court full of Franklin D. Roosevelt and Harry Truman appointees, with some strongly differing perspectives on law, was unable to reach a decision in early 1953. After the Republican governor of California, Earl Warren, was appointed chief justice by President Dwight Eisenhower, the case was reargued, and he corralled the disparate elements to a point of unanimity that left no doubt that an epochal page of history had been turned.

Although four other Eisenhower appointees would eventually join Warren on the court, his tenure there remained a beacon of liberal jurisprudence, which conservatives have battled back against ever since. You cannot really understand anything about the Supreme Court nomination process today if you turn a blind eye to this history. After Warren departed, Nixon tried to appoint two segregationists — G. Harrold Carswell and Clement Haynsworth — but they were both rejected. Shortly after that, Nixon nominated Lewis Powell (approved 89-1) and William Rehnquist (approved 68-26, the most ‘no’ votes of any successful nominee since 1930). Rehnquist was opposed by a record number of unions and organizations, including the NAACP, and lied about two significant racial aspects of his record. From then onward, one form of lie or another has figured significantly in the persistent conservative battle to turn back the hands of time and reverse the Warren court’s shining legacy that began with the Brown decision.

Generally speaking the lies take two main forms:

- a variety of different narrow lies about what specific individual judges have or have not done, and

- an array of broad lies about what judges in general should or should not do.

All are variants of one big über-lie: That only conservatives act properly as judges.

The first sort of lies most prominently involved Rehnquist and Clarence Thomas.

The second set of lies divided neatly into two mutually contradictory clusters,

- one represented by Antonin Scalia, whose doctrine of “originalism” says there’s only one right way for judges to approach the law (though he actually fudged things a lot, as we’ll see below), and

- the other represented by John Roberts (echoed by Neil Gorsuch today), who argues the exact opposite — that he uses everything he’s got, and doesn’t really have a philosophy at all, and it would be wrong if he did.

In between these two broad types of lies, there was one nominee who did not lie well at all: Robert Bork, whose nomination proved to be a turning point. With Bork, the lie machinery broke down, and he was rejected in a rare example of genuine public scrutiny and reflection. That resulted in a far more sophisticated approach to lying, both in the confirmation process itself, and in justifying judicial conservatism overall. To understand where we stand today, a review of all those mentioned will be helpful.


Rehnquist’s Racist Record Denied

In his two confirmation hearings Rehnquist lied about two separate issues. First, he lied about his personal, adversarial involvement in voter suppression efforts aimed at minority voters in Arizona in the late 1950s and early ’60s. Rehnquist admitted being involved in the efforts, but only as a legal advisor, while a former assistant U.S. attorney, James Brosnahan, and other eyewitnesses testified that Rehnquist had been personally involved in challenging and intimidating individual voters. Joe Conason gave an account of this in a 2004 Salon story;

Under oath, Rehnquist denied Brosnahan’s charges, and based on conflicting testimony from other witnesses, the issue was left sufficiently murky for the Republican-dominated Senate to confirm him. But in his 2001 account of that nomination battle, “The Rehnquist Choice,” former Nixon White House counsel John W. Dean concluded that Rehnquist — who said he didn’t “remember” engaging in voter challenges — had almost certainly lied to the Senate.
What’s more, a contemporaneous 1986 account from the Los Angeles Times provided first-hand testimony against Rehnquist from multiple witnesses. Those witnesses supporting Rehnquist were purely suppositional in character, and hence provided no true evidence at all.

The most obvious explanation is that Rehnquist and his supporters did not want us to know his actual record. But it wasn’t just his deeds they wanted hidden: it was also both his heart and his mind. In a 2005 Huffington Post article, Alan Dershowitz discussed the importance of a controversial memo Rehnquist wrote for Justice Robert Jackson in the 1950s:

As a law clerk, Rehnquist wrote a memorandum for Justice Jackson while the court was considering several school desegregation cases, including Brown v. Board of Education. Rehnquist’s memo, entitled “A Random Thought on the Segregation Cases,” defended the separate-but-equal doctrine embodied in the 1896 Supreme Court case of Plessy v. Ferguson. Rehnquist concluded the Plessy “was right and should be reaffirmed.” When questioned about the memos by the Senate Judiciary Committee in both 1971 and 1986, Rehnquist blamed his defense of segregation on the dead Justice, stating – under oath – that his memo was meant to reflect the views of Justice Jackson. But Justice Jackson voted in Brown, along with a unanimous Court, to strike down school segregation. According to historian Mark Tushnet, Justice Jackson’s longtime legal secretary called Rehnquist’s Senate testimony an attempt to “smear … the reputation of a great justice.” Rehnquist later admitted to defending Plessy in arguments with fellow law clerks. He did not acknowledge that he committed perjury in front of the Judiciary Committee to get his job.
A devastating 2003 blog post from Brad DeLong includes an excerpt from Richard Kluger’s 1977 book, “Simple Justice,” which presents some damning evidence against Rehnquist’s claim. As with the Arizona voter suppression case, it seems clear that if these issues had been raised in a trial court setting, Rehnquist could not have sustained his claims. It was the institutional presumptions surrounding the confirmation process that shielded him from the kind of scrutiny that could have led to a full disclosure of what had actually happened
.


The Lies of Clarence Thomas and the Truths of Robert Bork

A very similar dynamic occurred in 1991, when Clarence Thomas escaped from facing testimony about his pattern of sexual harassment in the workplace. The accusations against him made by Anita Hill had leaked out and caused a furor, but a similar accusation from another woman, Angela Wright, was buried by the Senate Judiciary Committee, under the leadership of Joe Biden. In 2010, Steve Kornacki wrote anexcellent summary for Salon of the overwhelming evidence against Thomas and how it was buried:

But Thomas also lied about another matter as well, when he claimed he had not debated Roe vs. Wade, and did not have an opinion about it — making him virtually unique among his law school cohort. But it was not just implausible; there is considerable evidence — both direct and indirect — that Thomas was lying about this as well. He developed strong opinions immediately after joining the court, for one thing.
n his 2001 biography of Justice Thomas, Andrew Peyton Thomas (no relation) reports three witnesses contradicting his self-characterization: Mike Boicourt, who served with Thomas in the Missouri attorney general’s office, Reagan’s Assistant Attorney General William Bradford and conservative media figure Armstrong Williams. Although the author chooses to soft peddle his conclusions, their testimony speaks for itself: Thomas had strong feelings about abortion and how Roe was decided long before he told the Senate otherwise.

Robert Bork was sandwiched in between Rehnquist’s nomination as chief justice in 1986 and Thomas’ nomination in 1991. The rough reception he received — actually being asked tough questions about his record, particularly by Ted Kennedy — went a long way toward shaping how future conservative justices would be presented. Thomas was one example: a black conservative using his skin color to inoculate himself against liberal criticism, as he succeeded Thurgood Marshall, and proceeded to fight viciously against everything Marshall had stood for.

Thomas further backed this up with an elaborate narrative of personal hardship, hard work and struggle against racism, for which he blamed liberals more than conservatives. It was rhetorically effective — thanks especially to Joe Biden — but not the sort of strategy that could easily be duplicated by others.

It’s important to recall what really happened with Bork. As Scott Lemieux summarized:

Kennedy’s opposition was based on Bork’s public record. Bork did publicly denounce the Civil Rights Act as not merely unconstitutional but based on a principle of “unsurpassed ugliness.” He did advocate for an extremely cramped interpretation of most civil liberties. He did believe that the Constitution provided no protection for a right to privacy. Republicans might have preferred that Kennedy not outline the consequences of these beliefs, but there’s no reason for Democrats to abjure accurate statements merely because they’re put in stark enough terms to be politically effective ….

“Borking” has become a conservative insult, shorthand to a political smear job. But the failure of the Bork nomination was anything but; it was an important moment that, among other things, saved Roe v. Wade from almost certainly being overturned. It says something about Bork’s constitutional vision that accurately restating his public views has become synonymous with the dirtiest of dirty tricks.

The Big Lie of Scalia’s “Originalism”

If Bork exposed what conservatives judicial philosophy was all about, then obviously they needed to hide it — but without being perceived as hiding it. Thomas showed one way to do that, but it wasn’t automatically replicable. What they needed was a general purpose way of getting themselves off the hook, a way of saying, “this isn’t my view, personally, this is what the law requires, period.” They needed some version of what I previously called an über-lie: that only conservatives act properly as judges

That’s where another nominee from this timeframe — Antonin Scalia, elevated right alongside Rehnquist — comes in. Scalia’s promotion of “originalism” provided a rhetorical framework for claiming authority without responsibility: He was only following orders—the true meaning of the Constitution. Don’t argue with him, he said, in effect: Take it up with James Madison and company. Or, when it came to statutory interpretation, take it up with a Congress of yesteryear.

Things really came to a head with Scalia’s “originalism” in the Heller case, reversing centuries of precedent, and finding an individual right to gun ownership in the Second Amendment, completely disregarding all that original text talking about “A well-regulated militia.” To defend what he had done, Scalia co-authored a lengthy tome, “Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal Texts,” which was eviscerated by conservative semi-maverick icon Judge Richard Posner, in a review scathingly titled “The Incoherence of Antonin Scalia.”

First, Posner explains that judges like to portray themselves in a passive, constrained manner, regardless of their actual judicial philosophy:

Judges tend to deny the creative—the legislative—dimension of judging, important as it is in our system, because they do not want to give the impression that they are competing with legislators, or engaged in anything but the politically unthreatening activity of objective, literal-minded interpretation, using arcane tools of legal analysis. The fact that loose constructionists sometimes publicly endorse textualism is evidence only that judges are, for strategic reasons, often not candid.
Posner then goes on to show that Scalia’s strict textual originalism makes no sense under even modest scrutiny, and he actually abandons it, but without fully admitting he’s doing so.

A problem that undermines their entire approach is the authors’ lack of a consistent commitment to textual originalism. They endorse fifty-seven “canons of construction,” or interpretive principles, and in their variety and frequent ambiguity these “canons” provide them with all the room needed to generate the outcome that favors Justice Scalia’s strongly felt views on such matters as abortion, homosexuality, illegal immigration, states’ rights, the death penalty, and guns.
In short, Scalia himself isn’t really a textual originalist — he just played one on TV. Posner also points out the elephant in the room:

It is a singular embarrassment for textual originalists that the most esteemed judicial opinion in American history, Brown v. Board of Education, is nonoriginalist. … Had the provision been thought, in 1868, to forbid racial segregation of public schools, it would not have been ratified.
This points to an essential truth: Even when writing constitutional texts we are constrained by the limitations and blind spots of our own time. To hold us hostage to the ignorance and prejudices of the past is to forever prevent us from moving forward into a richer, freer, more equal future.


John Roberts’ “Balls and Strikes” Lie

As Posner’s criticism suggests, there are insoluble difficulties at the heart of Scalia’s textual originalism. One response to this was a reformulation, dubbed “the new originalism,” which is yet another scam. But the other was to embrace the “57 canons” kitchen-sink approach, and this is precisely what John Roberts — and now Neil Gorsuch, following in his footsteps — have done. They pretend to have no judicial philosophy at all, just calling “balls and strikes,” as Roberts put it. So there’s no there there for anyone to object to. Liberals, in contrast, have biases and agendas, and want to “legislate from the bench”!

But, ultimately, it’s another version of the big lie: Conservatives, one way or another, do justice properly, while liberals do not. So only conservatives should be allowed to be judges. Sometimes it’s claimed that there’s only one right way for judges to act—the old or new originalism. Other times it’s claimed that only having no fixed approach makes for fair and neutral judges — again, meaning only conservatives. Both these arguments are lies, and lies that contradict one another. They all serve to hide what conservative judges are actually doing on the bench.

But there is another alternative — the real-life actual alternative, which conservatives are desperate to obscure — and that is for a judge to guided by an overall judicial philosophy. (Indeed, without such a philosophy, the shibboleths of “following precedent” and “judicial restraint” that Roberts invoked can become meaningless.) This point was made in the wake of Roberts’ confirmation hearing by constitutional scholar Ronald Dworkin in the New York Review of Books.

Instead of the Kabuki theater confirmation hearings had become, Dworkin explained what senators should have been looking for: First, a coherent set of “convictions about the proper role of a judicially enforceable constitution in a democracy,” and second, convictions about the role of judges in supporting, promoting or defending that role. Only these sorts of broad philosophical and constitutional commitments can give order and meaning to a judge’s interpretations, curbing political preferences on the one hand, while on the other giving concrete meaning to empty platitudes like “the rule of law.”

Such a judicial philosophy can take various different forms, Dworkin argued. “Scalia’s announced form of originalism, if in fact he held to it with any important degree of consistency, would constitute such a philosophy.” But he saw another alternative:

Justice Stephen Breyer, in his recent book setting out his own constitutional philosophy, offers a more attractive example. He argues that the liberty protected by an appropriate conception of democracy embraces not only a citizen’s freedom from undue government interference but a more active freedom to participate in self-government as an equal; and he undertakes to show that an understanding of the Constitution as aiming to promote that form of liberty can guide constitutional adjudication in several matters, including free speech, federalism, and the constitutionality of affirmative action.

I have myself defended a similar view of the Constitution: that it aims to create what I called a “partnership” rather than a majoritarian form of democracy by insisting that all citizens are entitled to an equal role and voice in their self-government, that government at all levels must treat citizens with equal concern, and that government must leave individual citizens free to make the personal decisions for themselves that they cannot yield to others without compromising their self-respect.
One doesn’t have to agree with Dworkin or Breyer or anyone else. The point is that multiple different constitutional philosophies are tenable, not as absolutes that everyone must submit to, but as hypothetical guiding frameworks. The proper role of the Senate confirmation process ought to simply be to ensure that a judge has such a philosophy to guide them, that they are reasonably clear and consistent in their ability to articulate it, and that it be compatible with our overall sense of what our Constitution embodies.

Several years later, the Alliance for Justice published two studies addressing the problems of ignoring precedent and lack of judicial restraint in the Roberts court. The first, “Unprecedented Injustice: The Political Agenda of the Roberts Court” highlights some of the most significant examples of the Roberts court ignoring and overturning precedent, while the second, “The Roberts Court’s Record of Overreaching,” focuses on judicial activism exemplified by disregarding long-standing procedural norms that no one ever dreamed of asking Roberts about during his confirmation:Taking cases that don’t require the court’s intervention, addressing legal questions that aren’t squarely before it, settling questions of fact rather than leaving that to trial courts, and making up new law out of thin air. What these studies showed in case after case was a pervasive pattern of actions wildly at odds with the “balls and strikes” imagery that Roberts used to get confirmed. And they were precisely what we should have expected, in light of the criticism that Dworkin offered at the time.


Three Relevant 19th Century Lies

None of this is new or surprising. If we look back to the 19th century, we find that the two most notorious racist Supreme Court decisions — Dred Scott and Plessy v. Ferguson — both rested on lies. Not just the broadly-shared social lie of black difference and otherness, but more specific lies, as well. On top of that, a conservative judicial philosophy emerged which pretended to embody the only possible way of interpreting the law.

First, Dred Scott contained this fateful passage, at the very heart of its reasoning:

They [blacks] had for more than a century before been regarded as beings of an inferior order, and altogether unfit to associate with the white race either in social or political relations, and so far inferior that they had no rights which the white man was bound to respect, and that the negro might justly and lawfully be reduced to slavery for his benefit.
This was simply a lie. The abolitionist movement had already begun at the time of the Revolution, slavery was abolished in Vermont in 1777, and was subsequently abolished in Massachusetts well before the Constitution was drafted. The later abolition came about in part due to a case involving a slave, Quock (or “Kwaku”) Walker, who was promised his freedom on his 25th birthday by his first master, but denied it by his subsequent master after his first master died. When he ran away, and his new master beat him, Walker sued his master for assault and battery — and won, with a judgment of 50 pounds. So there you have it, as plain as day: a black man with rights which the white man was bound to respect, bound by the judgment of a court.

The lies involved with Plessy are complicated, but I’ll highlight two of them because of how clearly they contradict one another. The first, perhaps most central, is that discrimination only hurts blacks because blacks think that it does:

We consider the underlying fallacy of the plaintiff’s argument to consist in the assumption that the enforced separation of the two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority. If this be so, it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction upon it.
This is clearly absurd, and the justices in Plessy knew it, because they also wrote:

Legislation is powerless to eradicate racial instincts or to abolish distinctions based upon physical differences, and the attempt to do so can only result in accentuating the difficulties of the present situation. If the civil and political rights of both races be equal, one cannot be inferior to the other civilly or politically. If one race be inferior to the other socially, the Constitution of the United States cannot put them upon the same plane.
So, in the first case, it’s all in black people’s head. At the same time, it’s far too deeply entrenched to be remedied by the Constitution. Both are obvious lies, and were obvious at the time to those not blinded by bigotry. But they are also mutually contradictory lies. A mythical “principled conservative” racist would choose either one or the other, not both.

Finally, as this brief essay from Harvard presents, a form of legal reasoning known as “classical legal thought” was formulated in the last third of the 19th century, and “dominated most American legal institutions until the 1930s,” when it was displaced by the school known as “legal realism.” While it had several different facets, what’s most germane to our discussion here is the one described here:

Meanwhile, an influential group of law teachers was elaborating its own version of classicism. Properly organized, law was like geometry, the teachers insisted. Each doctrinal field revolved around a few fundamental axioms, derived primarily from empirical observation of how courts had in the past responded to particular sorts of problems. From those axioms, one could and should deduce – through uncontroversial, rationally compelling reasoning processes – a large number of specific rules or corollaries. The legal system of the United States, they acknowledged, did not yet fully conform to this ideal; much of the scholars’ energies were devoted to identifying and urging the repudiation of rules or decisions that disturbed the conceptual order of their respective fields. But once purified of such anomalies and errors, the scholars contended, the law would be “complete” (capable of providing a single right answer to every dispute) and elegant.
Although there was more to classical legal thought than that, it epitomized the overall formalist obsession, and disregard for real world concerns, that had predominated in the pre-Civil War era, and that came to the fore once again with the legal realists who challenged it. This tells us, in short, that the conservative craving for a closed, unquestionable system of legal thought is nothing to new to our post-Brown vs. Board of Educationperiod. We have seen it before, and it has passed away before as well. The sooner we come to see through these lies, the sooner we will be rid of them.


Paul Rosenberg is a California-based writer/activist, senior editor for Random Lengths News, and a columnist for Al Jazeera English. Follow him on Twitter at @PaulHRosenberg.



SOURCE: http://www.salon.com/2017/03/26/gor...-lies-in-supreme-court-confirmation-hearings/


.
 

Camille

Kitchen Wench #TeamQuaid
Staff member
Let the Filibuster Burn!

Dry your tears, Democrats. In fact, cross your fingers that the Senate nukes the legislative filibuster, too.


Well before Mitch McConnell deployed the nuclear option to stop a Democratic filibuster of Neil Gorsuch, President Trump’s nominee for the Supreme Court, the judicial filibuster was dead. It was dead the moment Gorsuch was nominated, with Republicans eager to put him on the bench. The chance to confirm Gorsuch—or someone like him—was the reason Republicans launched their unprecedented blockade of Merrick Garland, the reason they backed Donald Trump after he captured the GOP presidential nomination, the reason they’ve looked the other way as Trump uses his newfound influence to enrich himself and his family. With Gorsuch and a Supreme Court majority on the line, there was no question that Republicans would do whatever it took to win confirmation. And if Republicans were ready to use the nuclear option in response to any Democratic filibuster of any high court nominee, no matter how justified, then in practical terms, the filibuster didn't actually exist.

The new fact of a 51-vote threshold for top judicial nominees raises a question: Will Republicans exercise the nuclear option to kill legislative filibusters as well? Democrats, if they choose, could adopt McConnell’s approach to Obama and slow the Senate to a halt with constant opposition, filibustering nearly everything that came to the floor, killing the president’s legislative agenda and retaliating for eight years of routine obstruction. Ending the legislative filibuster would rob Democrats of a valuable tool, smoothing the path for both President Trump and their colleagues in the House of Representatives.

That move—a drastic step that would reshape the chamber with consequences for everyone involved—is not currently on the table. “There is not a single senator from the majority who thinks we ought to change the legislative filibuster,” said McConnell to the New York Times. Still, the Times notes, Democrats don’t trust that McConnell won’t switch gears: “Do I believe Mitch McConnell would change the rules again? Yes,” Maryland Sen. Benjamin L. Cardin told the Times.

It makes sense that Democrats would worry; if they don’t fall in line, McConnell may strip them of one of their most potent weapons. But step back from the dynamics of the moment, and it’s clear there’s a case for letting the filibuster burn. For the health of the Senate—to say nothing of our democracy—Democrats should hope McConnell goes nuclear again.


The case for the filibuster is simple: The Senate is meant to be a deliberative body, and the filibuster helps sustain that deliberation, putting a break on the process when it moves too quickly, and forcing compromise and consensus among lawmakers. As appealing as it sounds—especially for those who lament the polarized, often acrimonious politics of the modern-day Senate—that case is ill-founded. Far from improving governance or political discourse, the filibuster impedes the former and does little for the latter. It adds further friction to an already countermajoritarian institution, incentivizes obstruction, and exacerbates the Senate’s already dramatic malapportionment. And despite a narrative that treats it as an integral part of our constitutional order, the filibuster was an accident—the unintended result of a minor Senate rule change.

Indeed, the filibuster wasn’t actually used until 1837, more than 30 years after its creation. As political scientist Sarah Binder once explained for the Brookings Institute, the filibuster didn’t enter regular use until the late 19th century, as the Senate—along with American politics writ large—became polarized on party lines. Even then, it was used sparingly, and was a subject of regular debate; throughout this period, majorities tried unsuccessfully to end it. The cloture rule—the 60-vote threshold that lets a supermajority end a filibuster—was negotiated in 1917, after Republican senators successfully filibustered President Woodrow Wilson’s effort to arm merchant ships. Demanded as a “war measure,” cloture as we know it was a compromise between Democrats who wanted a simple majority for cloture, Republicans who backed a cloture rule but wanted a supermajority requirement, and Republicans who preferred no rule at all. The filibuster is usually justified as a tool to help warring sides to reach agreement. But that is a fiction, a myth propping up an obstacle to lawmaking. (As the Atlantic’s Yoni Appelbaum points out, the notion of the Senate as a “cooling saucer” for the heat of the less deliberative House of Representatives was first circulated as a critique of the body.)

The ugly truth of the legislative filibuster is that, far more than being a tool for deliberation, its obstructive power has been put to the service of injustice. Segregationist senators, in particular, used the filibuster to kill civil rights and anti-lynching legislation, using the rule to protect and entrench regimes of terror and exploitation in the former Confederacy. In the present day, the filibuster does little more than prevent majorities from passing promised legislation and delivering outcomes to their voters. Which, perhaps, is the reason why it may well survive.

Ending the legislative filibuster, thus strengthening the majoritarian character of the Senate, clarifies lines of responsibility. Interested voters can see, more clearly, how and why legislation fails, a marked contrast to the status quo, where those lines are opaque. But greater transparency means greater accountability. Without the certainty of obstruction to fall on, parties may have to deliver on their promises, or at least modulate them, lest they make claims they can’t actually act on. It’s not hard to imagine why some senators, then, would prefer a world where the filibuster precludes serious action.



Liberal Democrats, at least, should want McConnell to nuke the filibuster, full stop. Absent a Republican filibuster—which gave huge leverage to the most conservative members of the Democratic caucus—the Senate might have passed a more progressive Affordable Care Act, climate change legislation, immigration reform, and even additional stimulus once it was clear the American Recovery and Reinvestment Act was insufficient. What they lose in the short term is more than compensated by greater freedom of action if and when they hold the majority. As it stands, the filibuster serves the “party of no” quite well. For those who have an agenda beyond tax cuts—for those who want the government to do something, and do it well—the filibuster is an almost crippling obstacle.

For that reason, it’s hard to believe McConnell would take the step of ending all filibusters. The ability to block large majorities is valuable for a party fighting to prevent any expansion of the welfare state. And even if McConnell wanted to take that step, it’s not clear his caucus would fall behind him. Ending all filibusters would change the Senate, forcing a generation of career politicians to adjust to a new reality. But while we’re thinking about the Senate and its rules, it’s worth remembering (and emphasizing) that taken as a whole, the filibuster is bad for governance. For all the challenges of a post-filibuster world, our democracy would work better if we confined it to the ash heap of history.

http://www.slate.com/articles/news_...ruth_democrats_are_better_off_without_it.html
 
Top